Relations and Multiple Quantifiers in Predicate Logic

Thus far we have been using only one-place predicates. These are predicates that only require one name (put differently, these are properties that only require one object) to complete them. For example,

_____ is red = Rx

_____ is heavy = Hx

_____ is a wife = Wx

(x)Rx is true if and only if there is at least one thing in the universe that is red. (x)Hx is true iff there is at least one thing in the universe that is heavy, and so on. (x)Rx is true iff everything in the universe is red, and so on. 

But, as we all know, there are predicates that are more than one place. In other words, there are predicates that require more than one name to complete them (put differently, there are properties-- better-called relations--that require more than one object). For example

____ is heavier than ____ = Hxy

____ is taller than ____ =  Txy

____ loves ____ = Lxy

____ is between ____, _____ = Bxyz

(∃x)(∃y)Hxy is true iff there is something in the universe that is heavier than something else in the universe. (∃x)(∃y)Txy is true iff there is something in the universe that is taller than something else in the universe, and so on (in some cases, the 'something else' clause is not needed. For example (∃x)(∃y)Lxy is true iff there is something in the universe that loves something in the universe and that something can be the same thing--if John loves himself then (∃x)(∃y)Lxy is true; it depends on the nature of the predicate). 

Now things get a bit trickier when we mix quantifiers. In general, the outermost quantifier has a kind of control over the entire statement (i.e. the outermost quantifier has the widest scope, it governs more of the statement). For example,

(x)(∃y)Lxy 

This states that for all x, there is a y, such that x loves y. Because the (x) is the outermost quantifier it governs the rest of the statement. So the statement says that for any x we choose there is something that it loves. Put differently, it states that everyone loves someone. 

(∃y)(x)Lxy

Note that the only thing we change was the order of the quantifiers. We did not change the order of the variables next to the predicate. So, this statement tells us that there is some y, for all x, such that x loves y. Because the (∃y) is the outermost quantifier it governs the rest of the statement. So the statement says that for some y that we choose everything loves it, loves that individual y. Put differently, it states that someone is loved by everyone. 

Notice what happens when we switch up the order of the variables. 

(∃y)(x)Lyx

This statement is quite different from the one above. It tells us that there is some y, for all x, such that y loves x. That is, there is someone who loves everyone (I wish I could say it was me :-(.






Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Predicates in search of nouns

Meta-Logical Themes: Soundness of Propositional Logic